Excellent. I’ll now review the full list of unsolved problems in physics and construct a table that maps each problem to how (or whether) it relates to the core ideas of your paper—including information-based time emergence, observer-dependence, and the reinterpretation of γ. For each problem, I’ll analyze whether your model offers a potential resolution, introduces contradictions, or simply remains agnostic. I’ll also call out any area that could falsify key claims if a certain physical observation holds. I’ll return with the completed table shortly. # Unsolved Physics Problems vs. Information-Based Spacetime Model Below is a comprehensive table examining each unsolved physics problem (as listed on Wikipedia) in light of the paper *"Time as the Fourth Dimension: From Atomic Rotation to Spacetime Emergence (Version 2.0)"*. The table assesses whether the model offers a potential resolution, conflicts with known approaches, or is not clearly relevant to each problem. It also notes if resolving that problem could falsify the model’s core assumptions. | Problem Name | Relevance to Info-Based Spacetime Framework | Interpretation or Proposed Mechanism (if any) | Risk of Falsification | Notes | | ------------------------------------------------------- | --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- | -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- | --------------------- | -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- | | Theory of everything | Potential resolution (conceptual unification via information) – The model aspires to link all physics by treating spacetime and forces as emergent from information, though it is not a complete formal theory. | It reinterprets mass-energy equivalence and force laws as information reorganization, suggesting a unifying principle, but provides no quantitative framework to derive all physical phenomena. | Yes | If a conventional TOE (e.g. a string theory or quantum gravity) is confirmed that requires spacetime as fundamental, it would conflict with the model’s premise of emergent spacetime, undermining the model’s validity. | | Dimensionless physical constants | No clear relevance – the model does not address the values of fundamental constants. | None. The framework offers no mechanism to calculate or reduce the number of arbitrary constants; it treats them as given inputs, just like standard physics. | No | This issue lies outside the model’s scope. Determining constants experimentally or via another theory neither contradicts nor validates the information-based model. | | Quantum gravity (unification) | Potential resolution – the model provides an alternative approach to unite quantum mechanics and GR by treating spacetime as emergent from information networks. | Gravity is reinterpreted not as a fundamental force but as a product of information "binding" between systems (no fundamental graviton), with Lorentz factor γ quantifying this linkage. | Yes | If a traditional quantum gravity (e.g. detection of a graviton or a discrete spacetime model) succeeds without needing the model’s information paradigm, or if spacetime is proven fundamental, the model’s premise would be contradicted. | | Black hole information paradox | No direct resolution but no contradiction – the model assumes information is conserved (in line with quantum theory), framing black hole boundaries as information horizons. | It doesn’t explicitly solve how info escapes a black hole, but it implies that information isn’t destroyed: e.g. any lost “binding” information is radiated or retained at the horizon (consistent with holographic ideas). | Yes | If it were demonstrated that black hole evaporation destroys information (violating unitarity), it would conflict with the model’s core view of physics as information-preserving. (Conversely, a resolution preserving information aligns with the model but is not unique to it.) | | Cosmic censorship & time travel (chronology protection) | Contradiction avoided – the model implicitly requires no violations of causality (closed timelike curves) or naked singularities, aligning with cosmic censorship assumptions. | Since time in this framework emerges from interactions in a consistent order, phenomena like naked singularities or time loops would break the informational flow needed for a well-defined “time.” The model therefore presumes these cannot occur (it assumes Hawking’s chronology protection holds). | Yes | Evidence of a naked singularity or a practical time machine (closed timelike curve) would undermine the model’s assumption that time has a globally consistent direction set by information exchange. | | Holographic principle | Supportive alignment – the model’s emphasis on information as fundamental is compatible with holographic ideas (physics described via lower-dimensional information). | It interprets boundaries like black hole event horizons as maximum information surfaces, echoing the idea that volumetric physics is encoded on lower-dimensional boundaries. However, the model does not provide a specific holographic dual; it simply embraces the notion of spacetime emerging from information entanglement. | No | Whether holographic dualities (like AdS/CFT) hold or not does not directly refute the model – the model can accommodate or survive the outcome, since it generally reinforces the concept of emergent information structure without hinging on one particular holographic scenario. | | Quantum spacetime (emergence of spacetime) | Central relevance – the model directly posits a mechanism for spacetime emergence (space from rotation, time from observation), addressing the question of how classical spacetime arises from a quantum/informational substrate. | It proposes that stable rotational motions create persistent spatial dimensions (providing reference frames), and that time appears only when systems interact (exchange information) externally. This offers a conceptual answer to how smooth spacetime could form from discrete events or relations, akin to other emergent spacetime approaches. | Yes | If empirical evidence or a more rigorous theory shows spacetime is not emergent from information (for example, it remains smooth and fundamental down to the Planck scale or emerges via a different mechanism like entanglement networks without needing “observers”), then this model’s core claim fails. | | Problem of time (quantum vs relativistic time) | High relevance – the model suggests a way to reconcile the conflicting roles of time in quantum mechanics vs. general relativity by making “time” observer-dependent and emergent. | In this view, time in quantum mechanics (normally a fixed background) is absent for truly isolated systems until they are observed, aligning with the relativistic idea that time is one component of dynamic spacetime unless an interaction defines a clock. The model implies that the flow of time in GR emerges once quantum systems interact and share information, thereby marrying the two pictures by making time relational and information-dependent. | Yes | If a conventional solution to the problem of time is found (e.g. a theory where a universal time parameter or a decoherence-based time emerges without requiring observers), it would cast doubt on the model’s claim that external observation is essential for time. Any experiment showing that an unobserved quantum system still experiences time progression indistinguishable from an observed one would falsify the model’s assumption. | | Yang–Mills mass gap | No clear relevance – the model does not engage with this purely mathematical existence and mass-gap problem. | None. It neither offers insights into the existence of a Yang–Mills theory nor the mass gap; those issues lie outside its information-centric scope. | No | Progress or failure in proving the Yang–Mills mass gap has no impact on the model, as it doesn’t depend on or predict anything about Yang–Mills theory. | | Quantum field theory (rigor in 4D) | No clear relevance – the model does not address the mathematical construction of QFT. | None. It assumes standard physics formalisms when needed and doesn’t propose any new formulation for quantum field theories. | No | The challenge of rigorously defining 4D QFT is independent of the model; solving or not solving it does not support or contradict the model’s claims. | | Cosmic inflation | Potential contradiction – the model’s implications about “time” emerging gradually conflict with the standard inflation scenario that presupposes a time evolution right after the Big Bang. | The model hints that early-universe time might not have been well-defined until information structures (observers) arose. This would challenge inflation, which requires a temporal sequence (fractions of a second after the Big Bang). The model doesn’t offer its own alternative for the inflationary epoch’s details. | Yes | Robust evidence supporting inflation (e.g. detailed CMB observations matching inflationary predictions) would pressure the model, as it must then reconcile how inflation proceeded when few or no observers existed. If inflation is essentially correct, the model’s notion of time emergence in the early universe appears inconsistent unless it can incorporate an observer-independent inflationary period. | | Horizon problem (cosmic homogeneity) | No clear resolution – the model provides no established explanation for the universe’s large-scale uniformity, apart from speculative ideas about information spread. | It suggests that because time and information exchange developed as the universe became complex, the early universe might have had different information dynamics. However, it doesn’t articulate a clear mechanism for equilibrating distant regions as inflation does. | Yes | If inflation (or another mechanism like a varying speed of light) remains the only viable explanation for homogeneity, the model’s lack of a comparable solution is a liability. The model would be challenged to remain credible unless it can account for the observed uniformity without standard inflation. Currently it neither contradicts nor explains the horizon problem, so it risks irrelevance if mainstream cosmology continues to succeed here. | | Origin and fate of the universe | Partial conceptual relevance – the model speculates on the origin of time and the role of observers, but does not offer a concrete cosmological origin scenario or prediction of the future. | It posits that in the very beginning the universe had “undifferentiated information” with no time, and that time **“started”** only as the universe gained internal observers (information differentiators). For the future, it implies if information processing ceases (e.g. in heat death), time would effectively stop. These ideas are philosophical and don’t address specific outcomes like a Big Crunch or Big Rip. | No | The model’s broad statements about the universe’s evolution aren’t specific enough to be falsified by typical cosmological observations. Whether the universe ends in a Big Freeze, Big Rip, bounce, etc., can be accommodated by the model since it doesn’t make quantitative predictions about those outcomes beyond suggesting that time exists only so long as information is being processed. | | Size of the universe | No relevance – the model does not concern itself with whether the universe is finite or infinite in extent. | None. The information-based framework is compatible with any overall size or topology; it addresses the nature of dimensions locally but not the global geometry of spacetime. | No | Discovering the universe’s size or curvature doesn’t affect the model’s claims, as they pertain to how space and time arise **locally** from matter’s information structure, not the universe’s global shape. | | Matter–antimatter asymmetry | No relevance – the model does not attempt to explain baryon asymmetry or CP violation related to it. | None. The emergence-of-time idea includes no mechanism for why matter dominated over antimatter; this problem lies in particle physics and cosmology beyond the model’s focus. | No | Any eventual solution for baryogenesis (or observation of primordial antimatter) has no bearing on the model’s foundations, since the model neither addresses nor depends on how this asymmetry came to be. | | Cosmological principle (large-scale uniformity) | No direct relevance – the model doesn’t depend on the universe being homogeneous, though it entertains the possibility of information-based anisotropies. | The framework can accommodate an inhomogeneous or anisotropic universe by attributing it to uneven distribution of information processing. It doesn’t require perfect isotropy (and indeed notes the potential of information “gradients” in cosmology), but it doesn’t predict specific departures from homogeneity either. | No | Whether the universe is ultimately homogeneous or has large-scale anisotropies doesn’t inherently contradict the model. Detection of intrinsic anisotropies might be interpreted as evidence of non-uniform information distribution, but the model itself did not uniquely forecast such features. Conversely, a strictly homogeneous universe poses no problem for the model; it remains largely unaffected by the outcome. | | Cosmological constant problem | No relevance – the model does not tackle why vacuum energy doesn’t gravitate as expected (the huge discrepancy in \$\Lambda\$). | None. The information paradigm hasn’t offered an explanation for the small observed value of dark energy or a cancellation mechanism for vacuum energy. | No | A solution to the cosmological constant problem (or continued mystery) does not impact the model, as the model has made no claims about vacuum energy or dark energy that could be contradicted by finding an answer. | | Dark matter (nature of) | Potential resolution – the model proposes an alternative explanation that the phenomena attributed to dark matter are due to “temporal information gradients” rather than unseen particles. | According to the model, regions with slower information processing (i.e. where “time runs” at a different rate) produce extra gravitational effects – flattening galaxy rotation curves and causing lensing – without need for new invisible mass. It posits that dark matter halos mark boundaries between different information processing rates, making them invisible electromagnetically (being out-of-phase in time) but still affecting spacetime curvature. The model even suggests tests (e.g. atomic clock networks or pulsar timing) to detect these temporal gradients correlating with dark matter regions. | Yes | If dark matter is empirically confirmed to be particulate (e.g. discovery of WIMPs or axions), or if precise tests show **no** time-flow anomalies in regions of high “dark” gravity, the model’s explanation fails. Its validity hinges on finding evidence for these proposed information-based effects; otherwise it stands contradicted by the prevailing dark matter paradigm. | | Dark energy (accelerating expansion) | No clear relevance – the model does not present a novel explanation for dark energy’s origin or value. | The framework has no specific mechanism for cosmic acceleration. It allows philosophical musings (e.g. perhaps acceleration ties into an “information horizon” or simply anthropic timing – observing the universe at the “right time” when dark energy and matter densities coincide), but provides no concrete alternative to a cosmological constant or quintessence. | No | The cause of dark energy (whether a true cosmological constant or a new field) can be accommodated within the model since it doesn’t tie any core proposition to how cosmic expansion works. Confirming a particular dark energy model wouldn’t directly conflict with the model’s claims, aside from the fact that the model itself has not illuminated this issue. | | Dark flow (anomalous large-scale motion) | No relevance – the model does not address this tentative observation. | None. If dark flow (a coherent motion of distant galaxy clusters) is real, it would likely be explained by gravitational pulls from beyond our observable universe, not by anything in the model. The model doesn’t propose an info-theoretic cause for such a phenomenon. | No | Whether dark flow is confirmed or ruled out has no impact on the model, as the model neither predicts nor relies on such large-scale motions. | | Shape of the universe (global geometry) | No relevance – the model does not speak to the 3D spatial curvature or topology of the cosmos. | None. Emergent spacetime in the model pertains to local dimensionality (3+1) arising from matter and observation; it doesn’t predict whether the universe as a whole is flat, curved, or what its topology is. | No | Any determination of the universe’s shape or manifold (flat vs. curved, finite vs. infinite, connected topology or not) would not contradict the model, since the model’s claims are independent of these global geometric details. | | Extra spatial dimensions | Partial relevance – the model leans toward dimensions being emergent rather than fundamental, and it emphasizes higher “information dimensions” (e.g. consciousness as a higher-dimensional observational perspective). | The framework implicitly suggests our perceived 3+1 dimensions are sufficient and arise from information processes. It doesn’t incorporate additional small spatial dimensions (like those in string theory). If extra spatial dimensions exist, the model would likely treat them as additional modes of information (or higher-order rotational degrees), but currently it has no role for them in its structure. | No | The discovery of extra spatial dimensions (or strong evidence ruling them out) doesn’t directly falsify the model. If such dimensions are found, the model might need to be extended to explain how they emerge or why they were hidden. However, since the model doesn’t explicitly deny extra dimensions (it simply hasn’t accounted for them), their existence would not inherently contradict the concept of emergent spacetime – it would just mean spacetime has more dimensions emergent from information than the model initially considered. | | Hierarchy problem (weak vs. gravity scale) | No clear relevance – the model does not address why gravity is so weak or why the Planck scale is vastly higher than the electroweak scale. | None. The information framework hasn’t provided a solution for the huge gap between the electroweak scale and the Planck scale; it doesn’t invoke mechanisms like supersymmetry or extra dimensions that conventional approaches consider. | No | A resolution of the hierarchy problem (or even if it remains unexplained) doesn’t affect the model’s core claims, since the model currently neither explains nor relies on the relative strength of gravity versus other forces. | | Magnetic monopoles | No relevance – the existence (or absence) of magnetic monopoles is not discussed or predicted by the model. | None. The model’s emergent spacetime idea doesn’t extend to explaining why we do or don’t observe monopoles; it stays silent on this question from grand unified theories. | No | Discovery or non-discovery of monopoles has no bearing on the model, as the model does not make any assertions related to magnetic charge. | | Neutron lifetime puzzle | No clear relevance – the discrepancy between two methods of measuring the neutron’s lifetime is not addressed by the model. | None explicitly. *(One could speculate that the model’s “information isolation” concept might affect particle decay rates – e.g. free neutrons observed vs. unobserved – but the model itself has not made such a claim.)* | No | If the neutron lifetime anomaly is resolved (e.g. an experimental error found or new physics like decays to dark particles), it neither supports nor contradicts the model, since the model made no prediction here. (Should an information-based cause be found, it would be serendipitous, but currently the model doesn’t posit one.) | | Proton decay | No relevance – the model has no comment on whether protons are ultimately stable or decay over long times. | None. Proton stability or extremely rare decay (as some GUTs predict) is beyond the scope of the information-based spacetime theory. | No | The observation or non-observation of proton decay would not directly challenge the model’s framework, which does not depend on this aspect of particle physics. | | Proton spin crisis | No relevance – the question of how a proton’s spin is carried by its quarks and gluons (the “spin crisis”) lies in QCD and is not touched by the model. | None. The model does not attempt to explain internal particle spin decomposition; its concept of “we are all spinning” refers to macroscopic or atomic rotation providing frames, not the quark-gluon spin dynamics inside nucleons. | No | Whatever solution emerges for the proton spin problem, it has no impact on the model’s validity, since the model operates at a different level (space/time emergence) and does not address this specific QCD issue. | | Grand unification (GUT) | Peripheral relevance – the model aspires to unify physics conceptually via information, but it doesn’t provide a GUT in the conventional sense of merging gauge forces. | The model’s unification is qualitative: it suggests all forces and particles might be understood as manifestations of information processes, but it does not propose a concrete unified gauge symmetry or a unification energy scale. It hasn’t derived the Standard Model parameters from a single theory. | No | The development of a successful GUT (or lack thereof) doesn’t directly falsify the model. The model could potentially accommodate a GUT by interpreting a unified force in information terms, but since it hasn’t offered its own testable GUT framework, its standing isn’t directly at risk from how this unsolved problem is resolved. | | Supersymmetry (SUSY) | No relevance – the model neither relies on nor rules out supersymmetry; it makes no mention of superpartners. | None. The information framework doesn’t consider supersymmetric particles or the mechanism of SUSY breaking; it operates independently of that theoretical conjecture. | No | Whether SUSY is discovered or excluded (e.g. at the LHC) has no direct effect on the model. The model’s claims about spacetime emergence remain agnostic to the presence or absence of supersymmetric particles. | | Color confinement (QCD) | No relevance – the model does not deal with why quarks cannot be isolated (color confinement). | None. Confinement is a deep QCD phenomenon outside the scope of the spacetime-emergence theory. The model doesn’t attempt to prove or explain the confinement of color charge. | No | Proving confinement analytically or discovering scenarios that challenge confinement wouldn’t intersect with the model’s domain. The model is unaffected by the status of this QCD problem. | | QCD vacuum structure | No relevance – complexities of the quantum chromodynamic vacuum (e.g. the θ-angle and condensates) are not addressed by the model. | None. The model doesn’t speak to the non-perturbative QCD vacuum or how QCD’s vacuum energy relates to spacetime or gravity (aside from acknowledging the cosmological constant problem, which it doesn’t solve). | No | Advances in understanding the QCD vacuum (or solving the strong CP problem via the vacuum structure) won’t conflict with the model, since the model provides no input on these strongly-coupled QFT issues. | | Generations of matter | No relevance – the model does not tackle why there are exactly three generations of quarks and leptons or their mass hierarchy. | None. It doesn’t provide insight into the pattern of fermion masses or mixing angles; those are beyond its informational spacetime scope. | No | Any theory that explains the generation structure (or even if it remains a mystery) does not conflict with the model, which operates on spacetime’s emergence rather than particle family specifics. | | Neutrino mass (Dirac vs. Majorana) | No relevance – the model offers no input on neutrino properties or how they acquire mass. | None. The nature of neutrino mass (Dirac or Majorana) and the mass hierarchy are not influenced by the model’s emergent spacetime ideas. | No | Determining the neutrino mass mechanism or hierarchy would not validate or falsify the model, as it’s orthogonal to those issues. | | Reactor antineutrino anomaly | No relevance – the model provides no explanation for the observed ν̄ flux deficit in reactor experiments. | None. If the anomaly is due to sterile neutrinos or mis-calculation, it’s a particle physics issue, not related to spacetime emergence. | No | Resolving this anomaly (finding a sterile neutrino or correcting the models) has no effect on the model, which does not engage with neutrino physics. | | Strong CP problem (and axions) | No relevance – the model does not weigh in on why QCD preserves CP (θ ≈ 0) or whether axions exist to solve this. | None. The mechanism (like Peccei–Quinn symmetry) that would make the QCD θ-angle vanishingly small is outside the model’s framework. | No | The model remains unaffected by whatever solves the strong CP problem (be it an axion discovery or another mechanism), as it doesn’t incorporate or challenge those QCD considerations. | | Muon \$g-2\$ anomaly | No relevance – the discrepancy in the muon’s magnetic moment is not addressed by the model. | None. This anomaly, hinting at possible new particle physics, is unrelated to emergent spacetime or information exchange concepts. | No | Whether the \$g-2\$ discrepancy is confirmed as new physics or resolved by refined theory, it doesn’t intersect with the model’s claims, so the model’s validity is unchanged by the outcome. | | Proton radius puzzle | No relevance – the disagreement in measuring the proton’s charge radius is not impacted by the model. | None. The model offers no explanation for why muonic hydrogen and electron scattering give different proton radii; this is outside its domain. | No | Any resolution of the proton radius puzzle (experimental systematic issues vs. new physics) has no consequence for the model, which does not concern itself with this level of subatomic detail. | | Exotic hadrons (pentaquarks, etc.) | No relevance – the model doesn’t address what combinations of quarks are possible or why some hadrons (like pentaquarks) are hard to find. | None. These are issues in hadronic physics and QCD; the model doesn’t provide insights into the spectrum of composite particles. | No | The existence or properties of exotic hadrons do not influence the model’s foundational ideas, since it operates at the level of spacetime and information, not the combinatorics of quark binding. | | “\$\mu\$ problem” in SUSY | No relevance – the model doesn’t engage with supersymmetric model-building issues like the \$\mu\$ parameter tuning. | None. That problem is specific to SUSY theories (why a certain Higgs mass term is \~ electroweak scale); the model does not involve SUSY at all. | No | Resolving the SUSY \$\mu\$ problem (if SUSY is even found) has no effect on the model, since the model is independent of supersymmetry and its associated puzzles. | | Koide formula (lepton masses) | No relevance – the mysterious numerical relation among charged lepton masses is not something the model attempts to explain. | None. If the Koide relation has deep significance, it pertains to pattern in particle masses – a topic the model doesn’t cover. | No | The model stands aside from this issue; finding a theoretical basis for Koide’s formula (or determining it’s a coincidence) would not impact the model’s premises. | | Strange matter (stable SQM) | No relevance – the model does not concern itself with the possible stability of strange quark matter or the existence of strange stars. | None. The existence of a stable strange-quark phase is a question for QCD and astrophysics, unrelated to emergent spacetime ideas. | No | Whether strange matter exists or not does not affect the model’s content or predictions. | | Glueballs | No relevance – the question of whether pure-gluon bound states (glueballs) exist doesn’t intersect with the model. | None. This is a hadronic physics question; the information-based spacetime model neither predicts nor precludes glueballs. | No | The discovery or non-discovery of glueballs is irrelevant to the model’s claims. | | Gallium neutrino anomaly | No relevance – the model provides no explanation for the observed deficit in certain neutrino source experiments (gallium anomaly). | None. This anomaly (possibly hinting at eV-scale sterile neutrinos) is a particle physics issue not related to spacetime emergence or information flow. | No | The model is unaffected by the resolution of this anomaly, since it does not engage with the details of neutrino interactions or new light particles. | | Solar cycle (sunspot cycle) | No relevance – the model does not address how the Sun (or stars) generate periodic magnetic activity cycles. | None. Stellar magnetic dynamo mechanisms are outside the scope of spacetime emergence or information theory. | No | The model’s validity is independent of the explanation for solar/stellar cycles, as it makes no claims in that domain. | | Coronal heating problem | No relevance – explaining why the Sun’s corona is millions of degrees hotter than its surface is not attempted by the model. | None. This is a solar physics problem (possibly involving wave heating or nanoflares) unsolved in standard physics; the information framework doesn’t contribute to it. | No | Whatever solution is eventually found for coronal heating, it doesn’t influence the model, which operates on different fundamentals. | | Astrophysical jet formation | No relevance – the model doesn’t tackle why or how certain accretion disks produce relativistic jets along their poles. | None. Jet launching and collimation involve magnetohydrodynamics and relativity (Blandford–Znajek mechanism, etc.), which the model does not modify or address with information-based concepts. | No | Understanding jets (or failing to) has no effect on the model’s core propositions about spacetime, as it’s an astrophysical phenomenon beyond the model’s purview. | | Diffuse interstellar bands (DIBs) | No relevance – the unidentified absorption lines in interstellar spectra are a chemistry/astrophysics mystery not touched by the model. | None. Identifying the molecules responsible for DIBs (and how they form) lies outside anything the emergent spacetime model would address. | No | Solving or not solving this spectral mystery has no impact on the model. | | Supermassive black holes (M–σ relation, early quasars) | No relevance – the model doesn’t explain the empirical relation between black hole mass and galaxy velocity dispersion, nor how quasars grew to \$10^{10}M\_\odot\$ so early. | None. Those are astrophysical evolution puzzles; the model’s focus on information and time doesn’t shed light on black hole seeding or feedback processes governing the M–σ relation. | No | The model remains unaffected by progress (or lack thereof) in understanding galaxy–black hole coevolution or early quasar growth, as it doesn’t integrate those details into its framework. | | Kuiper cliff (outer Solar System) | No relevance – the sudden drop-off in Kuiper Belt objects beyond \~50 AU is a solar-system-specific puzzle not addressed by the model. | None. Planetary formation and orbital dynamics issues are beyond the model’s focus on spacetime emergence. | No | Whatever explains the Kuiper cliff (e.g. undiscovered planets, migration history) has no bearing on the model’s validity. | | Flyby anomaly | No clear relevance – the small unexplained energy changes observed in some spacecraft Earth flybys are not accounted for by the model. | None explicitly. *(If anything, the model might attribute any tiny deviation to unmodeled relativistic effects or information-exchange nuances, but it provides no concrete alternative explanation.)* | No | Further investigation may find a mundane cause or new physics for the flyby anomaly; in either case, the model has made no claim about it, so it wouldn’t be contradicted or confirmed by the outcome. | | Galaxy rotation problem | Potential resolution – the model offers an alternate explanation to dark matter for flat rotation curves, via an additional “information-based” gravitational component. | It attributes the discrepancy between observed and Newtonian rotation speeds to an extra term \$g\_{\text{temporal}}\$, a gravity-like effect arising from gradients in information processing rate (i.e. “flow of time”) across a galaxy. Essentially, outer stars experience time slightly differently (due to less interaction), producing the effect of extra centripetal force without actual dark mass. | Yes | If observations continue to favor actual dark matter or modified gravity models that don’t involve time-flow differences, the model’s idea fails. For instance, if no evidence of the predicted temporal effects (e.g. clock rate changes or pulsar timing variations in different galactic regions) is found, or if dark matter particles are directly detected, it would falsify the model’s interpretation of rotation curves. | | Supernova explosion mechanism | No relevance – the model does not engage with the complex physics of how a collapsing stellar core turns into a supernova explosion. | None. Neutrino transport, fluid instabilities and other processes in supernovae are far afield from emergent spacetime concepts. The model offers no new insight into this problem. | No | Resolving the supernova mechanism (e.g. via improved simulations showing how the shock revives) doesn’t interact with the model’s claims, so it poses no risk to the model. | | p-nuclei nucleosynthesis | No relevance – the model doesn’t discuss the astrophysical processes that produce certain rare heavy isotopes (the p-nuclei). | None. This is a nuclear astrophysics question (likely involving supernova or neutron-star collisions) not impacted by or mentioned in the model. | No | The model is unaffected by how this nucleosynthesis problem is solved (neutrino winds, gamma-process, etc.), as it’s unrelated to spacetime emergence. | | Ultra-high-energy cosmic rays | No relevance – the model doesn’t tackle why some cosmic rays reach energies above the GZK cut-off or what their sources are. | None. Proposed explanations involve exotic astrophysical sources or new physics (e.g. super-GZK propagation), which the model doesn’t involve itself in. | No | Discovering the origin of \$>10^{20}\$ eV cosmic rays (or confirming the expected GZK limit) has no impact on the model’s validity, since the model makes no predictions in this domain. | | Saturn’s rotation period anomaly | No relevance – the puzzling variation in Saturn’s measured rotation period (via its magnetosphere) is not addressed by the model. | None. The model doesn’t deal with planetary interior dynamics or magnetospheric interactions that might cause the observed periodicity shifts. | No | Whatever explains Saturn’s period drift (e.g. a decoupled interior rotating at a different rate) does not relate to or affect the model. | | Magnetar magnetic fields | No relevance – the origin of extremely strong magnetic fields in magnetars is not explained by the model. | None. This is a question of stellar evolution/magnetic dynamo theory beyond the scope of emergent spacetime ideas. | No | The model’s framework remains untouched by how or why magnetars have \$10^{15}\$ gauss fields, as it’s not part of its premises or domain. | | Large-scale cosmic anisotropy | Peripheral relevance – the model can accommodate an anisotropic universe but does not provide a detailed cause for it. | It notes the possibility of intrinsic cosmic anisotropies and even suggests analyzing the CMB for patterns of information emergence. The model would interpret any large-scale anisotropy as indicative of uneven initial information distribution. However, it doesn’t itself predict specific anisotropic features; it merely is open to them. | No | If cosmic anisotropy is confirmed (violating the cosmological principle), it doesn’t contradict the model – the model is flexible enough to incorporate it as evidence of complex initial information conditions. If instead the universe is perfectly isotropic at large scales, that’s also fine under the model. Thus, while the model is open to anisotropy, it isn’t uniquely validated or invalidated by it due to lacking a specific predictive stance on the issue. | | Age–metallicity relation (Milky Way) | No relevance – the correlation (or lack thereof) between stellar ages and metallicities in the galaxy is an astrophysical detail outside the model’s considerations. | None. The model doesn’t engage with galactic chemical evolution or star formation history issues. | No | The presence or absence of a clear age–metallicity relationship in stars does not influence the information-based spacetime framework, since that deals with far more fundamental questions than the details of galactic archaeology. | | Primordial lithium problem | No relevance – the model does not attempt to reconcile the predicted vs. observed \$^7\$Li abundances from Big Bang nucleosynthesis. | None. This is a cosmology/astrophysics issue (possibly nuclear reaction rate uncertainties) that the model does not touch. | No | Whether this discrepancy is resolved by new physics or astrophysical phenomena (or remains an open problem) has no effect on the model’s viability, as the model does not address element abundances or early-universe nuclear chemistry. | | Ultraluminous X-ray sources (ULXs) | No relevance – the model doesn’t explain what powers non-AGN X-ray sources exceeding the Eddington luminosity in external galaxies. | None. This is an astrophysical puzzle (perhaps involving intermediate-mass black holes or anisotropic emission); the model doesn’t involve itself with such specific high-energy astrophysical phenomena. | No | Any understanding gained about ULXs (be it hidden black holes or beamed neutron stars) doesn’t interact with the model’s claims, so the model remains unaffected by progress on this front. | | Fast radio bursts (FRBs) | No relevance – the model doesn’t propose a mechanism for these millisecond radio flashes from distant galaxies. | None. Many models (magnetar flares, colliding objects, etc.) exist for FRBs, but the emergent spacetime model offers no insight here, as it is not concerned with transient astrophysical events. | No | Discovering the cause of FRBs (or even if they stay partly mysterious) has no bearing on the information-based spacetime framework, which is silent on this phenomenon. | | Cosmic magnetic fields (origin) | No relevance – the model does not address how large-scale magnetic fields (in galaxies and clusters) were generated in the early universe. | None. Magnetogenesis (possibly via primordial plasma processes or phase transitions) is not something the model’s information paradigm attempts to explain. | No | Solving the origin of cosmic magnetism is independent of the model, as the model neither helps with nor is challenged by this issue. | | QCD matter phases & cosmic evolution | No relevance – the model doesn’t delve into the phases of strongly interacting matter or their roles in the early universe. | None. Questions like the quark–hadron transition in the early Big Bang or the partonic structure of nucleons are outside the model’s focus on spacetime/information. | No | Advances in mapping QCD phase diagrams or connecting them to cosmology won’t conflict with the model, since the model provides no input on these phenomena. | | Quark–gluon plasma (QGP) | No relevance – the model doesn’t address the conditions for deconfinement or the properties of the QGP in heavy-ion collisions. | None. These are high-energy nuclear physics questions; the model does not engage with them or alter their expected outcomes. | No | Empirical findings about QGP onset, ideal fluid behavior, or strangeness production do not influence the model’s core claims. | | Gluon saturation & CGC (color glass) | No relevance – technical aspects of QCD (gluon saturation at high density, evolution equations like BFKL/BK) are beyond the model’s scope. | None. The model is not concerned with these detailed predictions of QCD at extreme densities. | No | Outcomes of research into gluon saturation or color glass condensate physics won’t affect the model. | | Nuclear structure & astrophysics | No relevance – the model does not attempt to explain nuclear forces, the EMC effect, neutron star EOS, or nucleosynthesis of heavy elements. | None. All these detailed nuclear physics questions (binding mechanisms, free neutron lifetime differences, origin of elements in stars) are not influenced by the emergent spacetime perspective. | No | Solutions to these nuclear problems (or even if some remain unsolved) don’t impact the model, as it does not tie into nuclear force models or stellar nucleosynthesis processes. | | Navier–Stokes equations (smoothness) | No relevance – this mathematical problem (existence and smoothness of 3D Navier–Stokes solutions) is unrelated to the model. | None. The model doesn’t contribute to or depend on proofs of classical fluid equation behavior. | No | The status of the Navier–Stokes problem (one of the Millennium Prize Problems) does not affect the model, since the model is independent of classical fluid mechanics issues. | | Turbulence (theoretical description) | No relevance – the model doesn’t help describe or predict the statistics of turbulent flows. | None. Turbulence is a notorious classical physics challenge not addressed by an information-theoretic spacetime model. | No | The difficulty or success in modeling turbulence has nothing to do with the model’s claims, so it poses no falsifiability risk to it. | | Granular convection (Brazil nut effect) | No relevance – explaining convection-like behavior in shaken granular media is outside the model’s domain. | None. This is a granular physics phenomenon unrelated to spacetime or observation in the model’s context. | No | The model is neither helped nor hindered by whatever explains granular convection; the topics do not intersect. | | Bose–Einstein condensation (BEC) | No relevance – proving BEC existence for general interacting systems (a mathematical physics problem) isn’t part of the model. | None. The model doesn’t assist in this theoretical proof in condensed matter physics. | No | The outcome of this proof problem doesn’t affect the model. | | High-\$T\_c\$ superconductivity | No relevance – the unknown mechanism behind high-temperature superconductors is not addressed by the model. | None. Electron pairing in complex materials is outside the emergent spacetime discussion; the model doesn’t propose any explanation for it. | No | Whatever ultimately explains high-\$T\_c\$ superconductivity (be it phonons, spin fluctuations, etc.) has no impact on the model’s validity. | | Glass transition | No relevance – the model doesn’t tackle why glasses behave as they do or how to characterize the glass transition. | None. This is a condensed matter phenomenon (the nature of the amorphous solid state) not influenced by spacetime emergence theory. | No | The model remains unaffected by progress in understanding the glass transition or glassy dynamics. | | Amorphous solids (low-\$T\$ universality) | No relevance – the puzzling universal low-temperature properties of disordered solids are not covered by the model. | None. The model doesn’t delve into solid-state physics of disordered materials (e.g. two-level systems in glasses). | No | Resolving this puzzle would not validate or refute the model, as there’s no connection between these phonon scattering observations and spacetime-information principles. | | Cryogenic electron emission | No relevance – the increase of photoelectron emission at very low temperatures (in photomultipliers) has no explanation in the model. | None. This is an experimental solid-state effect unrelated to spacetime or information flow. | No | The model isn’t impacted by an explanation (or lack thereof) for this phenomenon. | | Sonoluminescence | No relevance – the cause of light emission from collapsing bubbles in a liquid (sonoluminescence) is not addressed by the model. | None. This acoustic cavitation phenomenon is an unresolved problem in fluid dynamics and quantum physics, lying outside the model’s scope. | No | Finding a cause for sonoluminescence (whether quantum vacuum effects or chemical reactions) doesn’t touch the model’s claims or assumptions. | | Topological order (finite \$T\$) | No relevance – the question of whether topologically ordered quantum states can exist at nonzero temperature isn’t approached by the model. | None. This is a quantum computing/condensed matter question beyond the model’s interests. | No | The model isn’t affected by the eventual understanding of topological order stability at finite temperature. | | Gauge block wringing | No relevance – the mechanism allowing precision gauge blocks to stick (wring) together is not covered by the model. | None. This is a classical physics/metrology curiosity (involving surface films, etc.) unrelated to spacetime or information theory. | No | Whether this effect is explained by fluid adhesion, vacuum effects, or something else, it has no bearing on the model. | | Fractional Quantum Hall (5/2 state) | No relevance – the model doesn’t provide an explanation for the unusual \$\nu=5/2\$ fractional quantum Hall state or its possible non-Abelian quasiparticles. | None. This condensed matter phenomenon is outside the emergent spacetime narrative; the model does not deal with strongly correlated electron states. | No | The resolution of the 5/2 state’s nature (e.g. confirming non-Abelian anyons) does not intersect with or challenge the model. | | Liquid crystal phase transitions | No relevance – the model does not concern itself with phase transition universality in liquid crystal states. | None. Critical behavior in liquid crystal transitions is not related to spacetime emergence or observer-defined time. | No | Insights into nematic–smectic phase transitions have no effect on the model. | | Semiconductor nanocrystal optics | No relevance – the cause of non-parabolic energy vs. size scaling in quantum dot absorption isn’t addressed by the model. | None. This is a quantum-confined semiconductor property, unrelated to spacetime fundamentals or information theory. | No | The model’s viability is unchanged by whatever explains quantum dot optical properties. | | Metal whiskering | No relevance – the spontaneous growth of metal filaments (whiskers) on surfaces isn’t explained by the model. | None. It’s a materials science problem (possibly stress-driven or electrostatic) not tied to information or spacetime theories. | No | The model is not impacted by understanding or mitigating metal whiskers in electronics. | | Superfluid helium-4 anomaly | No relevance – the slight discrepancy in a critical exponent for helium’s superfluid phase transition isn’t handled by the model. | None. This is a precision measurement vs. theory issue in statistical physics, outside the scope of emergent spacetime. | No | The model stands apart from this issue; resolving it (via refined theory or experiments) doesn’t relate to the model’s claims. | | Scharnhorst effect (faster-than-\$c\$?) | **Contradiction potential** – the model assumes no information can travel faster than \$c\$, consistent with relativity, so a confirmed Scharnhorst effect (photons going *slightly* faster than \$c\$ in a Casimir vacuum) would conflict with it. | The model relies on the Lorentz factor and the speed of light \$c\$ as the ultimate speed for information transfer. It does not anticipate any scenario where signals genuinely exceed \$c\$ (even in altered vacuum conditions), aligning with standard causality. | Yes | If an experiment were to validate superluminal signal propagation between closely spaced plates (indicating \$c\$ is slightly exceeded in that special vacuum), it would violate a cornerstone of both relativity and the model’s information-binding limit. This would force a fundamental re-evaluation of the model (and indeed of conventional physics), as it hinges on the inviolability of \$c\$ for information exchange. | | Quantum computing threshold | No relevance – the model doesn’t address the error-correction threshold or qubit scalability challenges directly. | None. These are practical engineering questions for quantum computing, whereas the model concerns fundamental physics of spacetime. | No | Success or failure in building large-scale fault-tolerant quantum computers doesn’t test or impact the model’s principles. | | Topological qubits | No relevance – the feasibility of topological quantum computing (e.g. using Majorana zero modes) isn’t covered by the model. | None. The model doesn’t influence whether certain qubit implementations (topological qubits) will work; that’s a technological and condensed matter issue. | No | The model is unaffected by the outcome of topological qubit research or the discovery of stable Majorana modes. | | Quantum computing at room \$T\$ | No relevance – the model has no specific insight into whether quantum computation can operate at non-cryogenic temperatures. | None. This is a technological/material science question beyond the model’s scope. | No | Achieving room-temperature quantum computing (or failing to) has no bearing on the model’s validity or claims. | | Complexity classes (BQP vs NP) | No relevance – the model does not engage with computational complexity theory problems. | None. The relationship of quantum complexity classes (BQP) to classical classes (NP, etc.) is not influenced by emergent spacetime ideas. | No | Regardless of how BQP relates to NP or other classes (an open theoretical computer science question), the model’s framework remains untouched, as it speaks to physics, not computation limits. | | Post-quantum cryptography | No relevance – the model doesn’t address cryptographic security against quantum algorithms. | None. This is a computer science and mathematics issue, unrelated to the physics of spacetime. | No | Developments in cryptography (e.g. finding algorithms secure against quantum attacks) have no impact on the model. | | Quantum channel capacity | No relevance – the unknown capacities of general quantum communication channels (quantifying entanglement-assisted capacities, etc.) are not something the model tackles. | None. This is a quantum information theory question separate from spacetime emergence. | No | Resolving how to compute quantum channel capacities, or discovering new bounds, has no effect on the model. | | Fusion power & confinement | No relevance – the model offers no new solution to achieving sustained nuclear fusion or understanding plasma confinement (H-mode). | None. Those are plasma physics and engineering challenges beyond the model’s focus. | No | The feasibility of practical fusion energy does not relate to or challenge the model, as the model makes no claims in this area. | | Injection problem (cosmic rays) | No relevance – the model doesn’t explain how particles initially gain energies high enough for Fermi acceleration (the “injection” into cosmic ray acceleration). | None. Astrophysical particle acceleration mechanisms are outside its scope; the model does not propose anything here. | No | Solving the injection problem (identifying a mechanism or confirming it as part of shock processes) has no effect on the model. | | Alfvénic turbulence (space plasmas) | No relevance – understanding the turbulence in the solar wind and corona isn’t affected by the model. | None. Space plasma dynamics (Alfvén wave turbulence, etc.) are not addressed by the model’s information-based approach. | No | This remains a specialized space plasma problem with no bearing on the model’s content. | | Ball lightning | No relevance – the model doesn’t attempt to explain this mysterious atmospheric electrical phenomenon. | None. Ball lightning’s nature (whether plasma, oxidizing aerosols, or something exotic) is not touched by the model. | No | Any accepted explanation of ball lightning wouldn’t impact the model’s framework, since the model operates on very different scales and principles. | | Stochastic gene expression | No relevance – the model doesn’t deal with how genes can express with inherent noise yet yield robust outcomes in biology. | None. These are systems biology and biophysics questions, far removed from spacetime emergence. | No | The model remains unaffected by progress in understanding gene expression variability or developmental robustness. | | Immune system (quantitative) | No relevance – the model doesn’t address how to quantitatively describe immune network dynamics. | None. Immunology questions (like network theory of immune responses) are beyond the model’s scope. | No | This does not influence the model either way, as there’s no overlap with spacetime or information fundamentals. | | Homochirality (biomolecular handedness) | No relevance – the model doesn’t explain why biological molecules (amino acids, sugars) are overwhelmingly one chiral form. | None. This is a chemical/origin-of-life question, not related to physics of spacetime or observation. | No | Any proposed solution to homochirality (e.g. circularly polarized light, statistical chance amplified) doesn’t intersect with the model. | | Magnetoreception | No relevance – the model doesn’t cover how animals (like birds) sense Earth’s magnetic field. | None. Whether magnetoreception is classical or involves quantum coherence (e.g. radical pair mechanism) is not within the model’s considerations. | No | Findings about magnetoreception (quantum or not) neither support nor refute the model’s claims, as it operates on a different level of description. | | Protein folding problem | No relevance – the model has nothing to contribute to how proteins fold into their 3D structures so quickly and reproducibly. | None. Protein folding kinetics and the computational prediction of structure (recently advanced by AI) are biochemical issues outside the model’s realm. | No | Advances in solving protein folding (algorithmically or theoretically) don’t relate to the model’s spacetime-information ideas, so the model is unaffected. | | Quantum biology (coherence in life) | Peripheral relevance – the model touches on consciousness and observation but doesn’t specifically address long-lived quantum coherence in biological systems. | The model posits consciousness emerges from information processes (potentially spanning quantum and classical regimes), but it does not claim that typical biological functions (like photosynthesis efficiency or bird navigation) rely on quantum coherence. It’s compatible with such ideas in principle but doesn’t depend on them. | No | If quantum effects are proven crucial in some biological processes (or definitively ruled out), it doesn’t falsify the model. The model’s view of consciousness as information-based could accommodate either scenario, since it doesn’t insist on or deny sustained quantum coherence in life – it only asserts that whenever information is processed (quantum or not), time and potentially higher awareness can emerge. | | Quantum measurement (interpretation) | Potential resolution – the model offers an interpretation where wavefunction collapse and definite outcomes occur when information is exchanged (i.e. when an observation/measurement happens). | It effectively says that a “measurement” is an irreversible information update that gives time its arrow and the system a definite state. In this view, quantum superpositions persist until an external interaction (observation) forces an information exchange, at which point the wavefunction “collapses” and entropy (information for the observer) increases. This aligns with an information-theoretic interpretation of quantum mechanics (echoing Wheeler’s *“it from bit”* and other observer-dependent interpretations). | Yes | If experiment or theoretical progress showed that observer-independent mechanisms (like spontaneous objective collapse) cause wavefunction reduction, or if a many-worlds interpretation (with no special role for observation) gained empirical support, it would contradict the model’s insistence on external observation for state definiteness. The model could be falsified if, for example, isolated quantum systems were found to reach definitive outcomes *without* any interaction that could be construed as an information exchange (something standard quantum theory doesn’t predict either, but any deviation here would challenge the model’s premise). | | Arrow of time | Potential resolution – the model links the arrow of time to information and observation, suggesting the direction of time is set by increasing entropy/information and that the perceived “present” is an emergent construct of consciousness. | It asserts that time’s one-way direction (past→future) arises because each measurement or event increases total entropy (equivalently, adds information to memory), consistent with the Second Law. It also directly addresses the question of the **“present moment”**, claiming that the present is an emergent property of conscious information processing (our brains integrating information over a short window). Thus, the model’s view is that the thermodynamic arrow is fundamental and objective, while the psychological arrow (the sense of **now**) is an emergent, subjective effect of consciousness. | No | This explanation largely dovetails with existing physics (thermodynamics) and common philosophical ideas about consciousness and “now,” so it’s not introducing a risky new prediction that could be easily falsified. There is no obvious experiment that would refute “time’s arrow emerges from entropy increase and observation,” since it is consistent with all known physics. Only a very exotic finding – such as observing a systematic reversal of the arrow of time in an isolated system, or a violation of the Second Law – would challenge the model, but such a finding would upend much of physics, not just this model. The model’s take on the arrow of time is therefore more of an interpretive clarification than a bold new claim, and it doesn’t expose the model to additional falsifiability beyond what the Second Law already imposes on any physical theory. | | Locality (non-local phenomena) | Implicit assumption – the model assumes no superluminal information transfer, aligning with standard quantum mechanics in which entanglement creates correlations but not usable signals. | It doesn’t introduce any novel non-local interactions; instead, it emphasizes that information binding and exchange are constrained by relativity (the “information leash” is effectively the light-speed limit). The model acknowledges quantum entanglement but treats it as not violating locality in the sense of no faster-than-\$c\$ communication of information. | Yes | If non-local transmission of information or causal influence were ever observed – beyond the currently allowed passive correlations of entangled particles – it would violate the model’s fundamental assumption (as well as Einsteinian relativity). For instance, a definitive demonstration of controllable faster-than-light signaling or the exchange of momentum/energy in a non-local way would directly contradict the model’s reliance on relativistic causality. In such a case, the model would be falsified (along with much of modern physics). Short of that, so long as experiments continue to uphold that entanglement cannot carry usable information superluminally, the model’s locality assumption stands safe. | | Quantum mind (consciousness & quantum effects) | Partial relevance – the model addresses consciousness as an emergent **information** process, but not specifically through known quantum brain mechanisms. | It proposes consciousness arises when 3D information patterns (like those in a brain) are observed from a “higher” dimensional perspective, focusing on the idea that self-observation and rich information integration give rise to awareness. This view does not require quantum coherence in the brain (it’s compatible with classical neural networks producing consciousness through complexity), but neither does it exclude quantum processes in neural functioning. The model is essentially agnostic about whether phenomena like quantum entanglement in microtubules play a role – its emphasis is on the abstract information structure of consciousness rather than the physical substrate. | No | If it turns out quantum processes are crucial for consciousness (e.g. evidence supports Penrose–Hameroff’s ORCH-OR theory or other quantum mind hypotheses), the model can accommodate that by saying those quantum processes are part of the information-processing apparatus of consciousness. If instead consciousness is proven to be entirely explainable by classical neuroscience, the model is also fine, since it never insisted on a quantum component (only on an information/higher-dimensional observation component). Thus, experiments in neurobiology or cognitive science that confirm or refute quantum effects in the brain wouldn’t fundamentally contradict the model – they would simply detail the implementation of the “information processor” that the model says gives rise to time and consciousness. The model’s core claim is that consciousness is an emergent phenomenon from complex information observation, which can hold true regardless of the underlying physics (quantum or classical) enabling that complexity. | **Note:** In the table above, **“Risk of Falsification”** indicates whether resolving the unsolved problem (either by experiment or theory) could directly contradict the model’s assumptions. “Yes” means a particular outcome or discovery *would* conflict with the model, providing a potential falsification, whereas “No” means the problem’s resolution would not significantly affect the model’s validity. The **Information-Based Spacetime Framework** is most meaningfully tested by areas where it offers a distinct explanation (e.g. dark matter, the nature of time) and is largely unaffected by problems in domains it doesn’t address (e.g. condensed matter or bio-physics). Throughout, we have adopted a critical stance, noting where the model’s claims are speculative or potentially at odds with established physics, to ensure honest scientific scrutiny of its explanatory power and internal consistency.